By Richard
Walther Darré
Reich Minister
of Food and Agriculture, Reich Farmers’ Leader, Reichsleiter
of the National Socialist Party
From
the doctrine of the law of the state, as it has been taught hitherto, the
conventional view is well known: To a state belong:
1. a Volk,
2. a national
territory on which the people live,
3. a state power.
It has long been
recognized that these three basic components of the state: „Volk“, „It is
precisely this inner connection of a people with its territory and with its
state order that makes a state unique and gives it its living character, i.e.,
makes a problem of organization a living organism. It is precisely this inner
connection of a people with its territory and with its state order that first
constitutes the peculiarity of a state and first gives it its living character,
i.e. makes a vital organism out of a problem of organization. Thus, it is no
accident what kind of people lives on its soil and what kind of state authority
is established by this people on its territory. From this alone it is evident
that the State - at least according to our conception - is not characterized by
the idea of an unlimited perfection of power over its people and in its
territory, but that the power of the State is exhausted from the special kind of
interaction in which the life-legal forces of the people, the formation of its
soil, the willpower of its leaders, and the nature of the State’s structure
interpenetrate each other and are united into a unity. It should not be
overlooked that the State is also conditioned by the manifold forces acting
outside its borders, and that even in peace it must assert itself against these
external influences. In particular, we wish to emphasize that the character of
our State is not determined by foreign territories, as is characteristic of the
great colonial empires, nor by a foreign population which is only subject to the
power of the State, but that our State has its centre of gravity in its own life
and in its own people, and that it must develop its concept of the State on this
basis. This soil and this people provide our State with its tasks; at the same
time, they offer the natural forces which make possible and limit the
development of State power and determine its nature.
The special
relationship of the people to the State has always been the subject of
scientific and constitutional consideration, and today it has gained increased
importance in the cooperation between the Party and the authorities, and in the
division of public administration into State administration and the tasks to be
left to self-administration. As an example of such self-administration, I will
cite here only the corporatist structure of the National Socialist food
industry. Here the markets for agricultural products were organized for the sake
of the public necessity of a secure state food basis with the help of a
self-governing association under public law. In such self-administration the
interplay of state objectives, necessary for the sake of the whole, and state
outlook on the one hand, and an orderly self-administration of the economic
forces on the other, is shown - a practical example of the interlocking of the
forces of the people and the state. The inner connection between the formation
of the state and the people in the sense of blood-related connections between
the people has also been recognized and appreciated for a long time - especially
thanks to Romanticism and philosophical German idealism. National Socialism was
able to build on these intellectual traditions with its concept of people and
state. In our time, the connection between state and territory has also been
scientifically clarified; I recall only the work in the field of geopolitics,
which examined the influences of space on historical processes and in many cases
uncovered connections that are worthy of serving in the future as prerequisites
for a statesman’s store of knowledge. On the other hand, it seems to me that up
to now science has not paid sufficient attention to the relationship of the
people to the soil, at least not in the sense of the life-legal effects of the
land on the people and the life-legal community of destiny existing between the
two.
The connection
between the people and the soil on which they live is not exhausted by the fact
that the condition of the soil, the yield of the soil, and the mineral resources
have a natural influence on the economy and the material conditions of the
culture of this people. Early historical research and modern racial research
have already pointed out the importance of the type of soil and the formation of
the terrain for the settlement history of the people. But if we go beyond the
general influence of the soil on the conditions of life for a certain race and a
certain national life, and if we ask about the particular way in which a people
itself forms its relationship to the soil, in what form it owns and administers
the native land, this question can only be answered by the law of the soil. Land
law determines how the land is assigned to the life-legal forces of the people.
Thus, in practice, land law at the same time decides the internal structure of
the state. This basic truth can also be extended to say that land law inevitably
determines the future of a state. I even maintain that there is no Germanic or
Indo-European state which did not undergo a transformation of its land law
before it became extinct in history. The decline of these states is always
preceded by a revolution of their land law, often unconscious to themselves and
very seldom noticed by our historians, which in the first place creates the
preconditions for bringing the vitality of their statesmanlike blood to a
standstill.
In this respect the
conditions in Sparta are most clearly shown, where the fate of the hereditary
courts of the Spartiates, created by Lycurgas, and the fate of the Spartan state
quite clearly go hand in hand. We have such excellent clarity about these
connections in Sparta because Busolt, who unfortunately died too early,
investigated them in detail and brought them into the light of judgment. We do
not yet possess very many similar investigations of other states of
Indo-Germanic and Germanic type. But these few investigations already clearly
show that the assertion I have just made is justified, as soon as one approaches
the problem of the rise and fall of states of Indo-Germanic and Germanic nature
from the point of view of the relation of their land law to these events. I
consider these connections to be so decisive and significant that, in my
opinion, they would justify the establishment of a chair at every German
university.
The political
effect of the current law on land is conditioned in particular by the fact that
land and the work on it have always had a persistent, constant character. The
arable land does not yield a quick profit - as, for example, a block of shares
does in times of rising economic activity or as other movable assets do - but
the arable land requires constant care, which is determined by the nature of the
soil. This peculiarity of land cultivation has always resisted a rapidly
changing right of ownership and has favoured a consolidation of land rights,
such as is known in legal history under the word of the transformation of
personal property rights into urgent and hereditary rights to the land.
Especially the actual cultivation of the soil forces the peasant family into the
service of the field and the farm, and thereby connects the generation growing
up on it so firmly with the soil that the subordination of the family to the
laws of the field is felt to be the natural thing and a self-evident
commandment. From this, in turn, springs the custom or law that only one of the
blood heirs should later carry on the business, lest the law of the farm and
field should suffer by division of the inheritance. Let us compare this bound
property, which requires of the owner a certain way of life and daily work, with
a banked estate. This contrast may make it clear that such a movable capital
cannot point the way to the work of the next generation and cannot form an
obligatory tradition as, for instance, the ownership of a farm can. That is why
the arable land is the place of firm tradition and constant custom. This is what
gives land law its political significance. For the viability of every state
leadership is conditioned by certain basic laws of constancy, and these
character traits necessary for this develop more easily or more exclusively in
the rural population than in the structuring mass of a non-rural population
driven by aspects of economic conjuncture.
According to this
it is to be understood that, as far as the historical tradition reaches, the
right to the soil has formed a core question for the building up and downfall of
states, and that especially in our time, in the revolutionary transformation of
the neighbouring regions to the east, the agrarian reforms there are at the
centre of events. I may point out that the Russian state to this day sees in its
agrarian constitution the core of its internal political power. According to
this alone, it would be clear that a lasting agrarian constitution pointing to
the future was a fundamental necessity for the construction of the Third Reich.
Instead of this, under the influence of the BGB. all rural steadiness threatened
to flow away completely and thus to achieve the opposite of what the value of a
rural population is. The possibilities of indebtedness, and with it the burden
of interest, as well as the dependence on an immense, unregulated market, which
was dominated by foreign influences, brought the peasant holdings more and more
under the dominion of a foreign creditor capital. And while the BGB protected
this creditor capital and its creditors to the greatest possible extent, it had
not even included the word „peasant,“ this primal concept of all steadfastness,
in its vocabulary, let alone bothered about a peasant right. From this arose the
task of the National Socialist legislation to re-establish a firm land law and
to secure the economic existence of the peasant farms through orderly sales on
the markets. But if we want to fully grasp this significance of land law in the
German state of today, we must go deeper and ask, beyond the value of an
enduring firm agrarian constitution, what the peasantry means to our people. And
here the peculiarity of National Socialist agrarian policy becomes apparent in
comparison with the agrarian policy of other states. For us, too, it is
indispensable to link the holders of the right to the soil firmly to the
structure of the State, i.e., to do justice to the political significance of
land ownership; and we have therefore united all peasants and farmers in a
public-law organization, the Reichsnahrstand, which is closely linked to the
State and the Party in terms of personnel and administration. It is also our
duty to create the economic prerequisites not only to maintain domestic
agriculture, but also to enable it to achieve the best possible increase in
output. Only a few years ago, the future of German agriculture was envisaged as
being based on the American model of farming, i.e. an agricultural economy
geared to maximum profits, dependent on the economic cycle and calculated on the
basis of stock market capitalist profitability. As we know, farming has
collapsed in the United States today. If our peasantry had really adapted to
this farm economy, most farms would be at a standstill today, the country would
be desolate, and we would probably not be able to fight a battle of production.
Instead of this, the German rural economy is today in the midst of the battle of
production, in order to secure freedom of nutrition, i.e., the minimum
requirements of the people from their own soil, thus relieving our foreign trade
balance and freeing up means of payment for the import of industrial raw
materials.
The National
Socialist agricultural policy shares this objective with the nationalist
agricultural policy of other countries, for example, of the fascist Italy. The
peculiarity of our method, however, lies in the fact that we combine the
economic policy goals with the population and cultural policy necessities and,
in short, bring politics and economics into harmony in the sense of the one
summarizing and dominating idea of National Socialism. National Socialist
agricultural policy is concerned not only with the food economy, but at the same
time with the preservation of the peasantry as the blood source of the people.
And this last circumstance is very decisive and fundamental. For it is the first
time that the conclusion has been drawn from the fact that in a state of a
Germanic nature blood is preserved and multiplied in generations only in the
countryside, but that the turning away from rural life causes a strong attrition
of the sexes. If we may use the comparative image, we may say that the blood of
a people bubbles up, as it were, like a spring on its farms, only to dry up
sooner or later in the city. For peoples whose basic character is nomadic, for
example for the Jewish people, this law does not apply; on the other hand, it
applies absolutely to Germanic blood and can be called the iron law of fate of
Germanic humanity. National Socialist agricultural policy has conceived its task
in the light of these fundamental ideas: by means of the same measures it
attempts at the same time to secure the nourishment of the whole people and to
guarantee the preservation of farms and farming families in their capacity as
the blood source of the people. We know that the number of births in the
countryside is greater in proportion to the number of the population than in the
cities. In 1927 the average birth rate in the Reich was 10% lower than the birth
rate needed to maintain the population: in the country, on the other hand, there
was a birth surplus of 13%! In 1933 the birth rate, calculated per 1000 of the
resident population, was 18 live births per 1000 in the municipalities with less
than 2000 inhabitants, i.e., in the rural municipalities, in the middle group of
municipalities from 2000 to 400,000 inhabitants only 14.5 per 1000, and in the
large cities only 11.2 live births per 1000 inhabitants. But it is not only a
question of the numerical existence of our people, but also of the preservation
of the hereditary factors to which we owe all the efficiency and all the
achievements of our people. Here the one-sided movement of the aspiring forces
from the countryside to the cities in connection with the development of
metropolitan civilization means a danger.
The Swedish
population politician Professor Lundborg, Upsala, once described the cities as a
„traps“, which he’d use to describe the places from which the bearers of good
hereditary traits are lured and where their hereditary traits are wiped out in a
few generations. It is necessary to realize clearly the whole dreadful
implications of this realization. Everything that has ever been accomplished in
the German people has been accomplished out of its hereditary stock, which, in
accordance with the circumstances, knew how to master the tasks that presented
themselves. The liberal-democratic delusion that talent can be replaced by
education is today recognized in all its hollowness. But talent depends on
heredity, as we know. But if this is so, then our people has only one absolute
asset, namely the hereditary values of German blood, which it possesses and
which will continue to give it, centuries from now, the leaders and inventors it
needs to prove itself equal to the tasks of those centuries and thus to be able
to assert itself as a people among other peoples. No material economic
prosperity, no treasures of the world will secure the future of the German
people as much as the germs of valuable hereditary material which it possesses
today.
Today we make
balance sheets and statistics about all areas of our national existence, but
unfortunately none about the biological foundations of our national life. And we
are still further away from being able, on the basis of an impeccable biological
balance sheet of our national body, to also to draw up a biological budget for
once. Like a parvenu who has become rich overnight, we do not yet have any
relationship to what has made us rich and, like him, waste his money on our
precious blood. With cold hearts we watch our most precious blood lying idle or
wasting away, and in this respect we act like a fool who throws precious stones
with full hands into the sea where it is deepest and no soul will ever see them
again. In this connection I am reminded of a truly revolutionary word by Gustav
Frenssen, who once related in „Seagulls and Mice“ (page 247): A clever man told
me that, travelling in Thuringia, he had seen in the train a young man who had
been similar to Goethe in his whole appearance, and thought that there was
probably more than one of Goethe’s blood living in Thuringia and around there. I
think that this is indeed the case and said: „It is a pity that there are not
more. The time will come when, in the name of religion and morality, they will
emasculate those of bad heritage and demand many children from a man like
Goethe.“So much for Frenssen! And if we are not yet able to accept this last
mental demand of a thinking poet because of its novelty, we must be fools if we
do not want to do something against the fact that our rural source of blood is
drying up as a result of the law hitherto in force and is wasting itself
uselessly in the non-rural sector of our national existence. And all this after
all history proves to us that our culture is conditioned by Germanic blood and
that this, in turn, depends for its viability on the land law under which it
must live.
The basis for the
rural exodus of the enterprising and capable in the course of the last century
was the spirit of liberal capitalism and its liberal land law. Liberal
capitalism impelled man to follow only the pursuit of profit; as a result of the
economic opening up of the world that began through it and with it, it brought
high prospects of profit in urban industrial occupations. The peasant, however,
was plunged into uncertainty as to whether he would find any market at all for
the yield of his land and his labour, and what fluctuating price he could
expect. The land law of liberalism valued the possession of farm and field no
differently from the possession of movable property embodied in papers, and
allowed the same legal transactions and the same right of inheritance for both.
The BGB. stabilized liberalism legally and thus broke the baton over every
German peasantry that stood on the soil, but with it also broke the baton over
every affirmation of the laws of blood in the German people. This dangerous gap
in our legislation, which was in the offing in the 19th century, was correctly
recognized from the outset by Ernst Moritz Arndt, the farmer’s son and scholar.
I quote from his writing „On the Care and Preservation of Forests and Peasants
in the Sense of a Higher, i.e. Human, Legislation“, published in 1820: „Persons
must be free, but when sticks and stones and forests and mountains pass from one
hand to another like feathers in the wind, when even the most solid things
become mobile and fleeting, then nothing remains solid in people, even in that
which should make the laws unshakeable in the mind. But the two classes of men
who preserve this core strength of a people most simple mindedly and intimately
are the peasants in the country and the craftsmen in the cities. But these lose
all their solidity and all their moral conduct when, in the country, the farms
and estates of the peasants are made easily alienable and when, by dissolving
the guilds and introducing the praised general freedom of trade, the last old
strictness and discipline of the trades is broken through. It cannot be said
enough to an age staggering along in the deluded fraud of liberty, that all is
not liberty which has the appearance and name of it.“ And elsewhere: “This few
have considered, that if everything is left free, nothing remains free, but a
state of dissolution and debauchery must necessarily arise, which kills freedom
in its germs. This is the secret of true liberty, that by many material bonds,
by institutions which relate first to things apart from him, and only in the
third and fourth instance to him, man is kept and urged to discipline and order,
and to that sacred sense of the steady and abiding, without which no good
citizens can be.“
So much for Ernst
Moritz Arndt. For the National Socialist agrarian policy, the tasks arose from
this insight: On the one hand, the liberal- capitalist attitude in the peasantry
had to be eliminated, and the conditions must be created so that the farmer and
his children, instead of being guided by a capitalist striving for economic
growth, once again become proud of their own kind and remain faithful to the law
of life of the peasantry. Only by cultivating the peasant spirit can we hope to
keep precisely the valuable peasant children as peasants in the countryside, and
that on the old and on the new settlement farms. In this way we are already
directly preventing the extinction of the best hereditary stock. The
prerequisite for this change of attitude among the rural population was,
however, the detachment of agriculture from the capitalist cyclical economy and
the establishment of a steady economic form corresponding to the natural
conditions of arable farming. On the other hand, it was necessary to create the
land law corresponding to the peasant law of life. For a peasant attitude cannot
be maintained in the long run if the law denies it recognition, i.e., in our
case, if the development and continuity of a peasant attitude is counteracted in
the law of succession by the legal equalization of arable land and pecuniary
property. The National Socialist agrarian legislation serves both tasks, a
down-to-earth economy and a land law affirming the peasantry. The market system
creates fixed prices and secure sales for all agricultural products. It thus
re-establishes a down-to-earth economic form for the farms, makes the farmer
independent of the influences of the stock exchange and fluctuating economic
cycles, and frees him to serve the people’s nutrition. It is not the striving
for temporary maximum profits through a one-sided increase in this or that
branch of production, but the striving for a general increase in yield through
the most versatile possible cultivation of all the forces of the peasant
enterprise that becomes the driving demand for the peasant. This also
corresponds to the life-law of the farm and the best traditions of German
peasantry. The rural form of economy is legally secured by the corresponding
land law, which is also linked to the rural tradition of Germany. It corresponds
to the peasant thinking of the Germanic people that the farm and the field are
not a capital arbitrarily available for the purposes of one generation, but an
inheritance handed down from ancestors and to be passed on to the descendants.
It is an ancient German legal tradition that land and soil are not to be counted
among the landed property.
The living
generation has to administer and maintain the inheritance, and for its needs it
is entitled to the income it earns from it. The peasant custom brought this view
to bear even at the time when the law had alienated itself from peasant thought
and regarded the property of a peasant in inheritance as divisible as a sum of
money. Here the custom of transfer contracts practically preserved in large
areas an undivided inheritance of the farm.
But the conflict
between the legal possibility of division and the peasant custom of undivided
inheritance endangered peasant customs and attitudes. This can be seen in
particular in the numerous state laws on inheritance of the 19th century.
Although they were aimed at transferring the farm to an heir, the calculation of
most of these laws on inheritance, the settlement shows that they basically
count the farm as part of the mass to be divided and calculate the rights of the
individual co-heirs from this mass according to head shares; the farm is here
already regarded as capital, the value of which - even if after deduction of a
so- called „ advance“ for the an heir - is to be distributed. If the peasant
tradition were to be restored, that the farm serves the clan, the coming
generations no less than the present and the past, then the farm had clearly to
be taken out of this capitalistic calculation of inheritances or settlements.
This cleared the way in the law of hereditary farms, in accordance with ancient
custom and law, to use the proceeds of the farm for the needs of the living
generation, and to enshrine this purpose in the law itself. Now the descendants
of the farmer, who are soft heirs, have again been given the right to equipment
and vocational training in accordance with the proceeds, and for emergencies the
right of home refuge on the farm. Thus the rights of the clan at the farm are
preserved. Thus a new, but very old German legal concept of property has come
into effect in the farm and the connection between old custom and valid law has
been restored. The influence of custom and of the peasant’s own outlook on the
shaping of law in individual cases is secured by the fact that the terms of the
law of inheritance correspond to peasant and National Socialist thinking itself:
Ackernahrung,
Bauernfahigkeit, peasant honour are the prerequisites for the Erbhof. The
interpretation and application of these terms is placed in the hands of courts
in which peasants participate alongside judges. Thus, as far as this is legally
possible, a guarantee is given for the harmony of law and custom, and a legal
basis is created for the peasant way of thinking. One is generally less aware of
the fact that an old peasant demand from the time of the peasant wars has
finally been heeded. As a people becomes conscious of its own values in its law,
so does the individual estate become conscious of itself in its law. This is why
the right of inheritance is the basis for a peasant’s own self-awareness and
thus for the strengthening and purification of the peasant’s conception of
marriage. I have emphasized the connection which links all the measures of
National Socialist agricultural policy. We have seen the questions of the food
economy in their connection with the questions of the peasantry, and we have
regarded the peasantry at the same time as the nutrient state and the blood
source of the people. The unified approach, which brings together the economic,
legal and political tasks of the population and integrates them into the overall
task, is rooted in the National Socialist view of the vital unity of the farmer
and the farm, the people and the soil.
This brings me back
to my starting point. The connection of our people with its soil can neither be
grasped only economically, nor is it a mere question of the distribution of
power in the state. The connection of our people with its soil is rooted in the
peasant character of our people and in the indissoluble unity of life of the
peasantry in the Germanic-Germanic sense with its arable soil. The field can
bring a steady yield and enables the generation that tills it to last forever,
as far as we can see. The sex that cultivates the field can attain such duration
if it maintains the field and itself on it in a form of law and economy
corresponding to arable farming. The agrarian legislation has nothing else to do
than to give validity to this vital law of the peasantry of our people under the
present conditions of our national economy and to secure it in the form
necessary today. The National Socialist land law and the land- based economic
system with its market order are based on this. It is on this that the
population and food security of the State is based. In this sense, the law of
unity of blood and soil is a fundamental idea of the National Socialist concept
of the state. And this concept of the state of blood and soil differs
fundamentally from all merely nationalistic concepts of the state in that it
makes blood, i.e. race, the axis of its world view and of all political
considerations, whereas the purely nationalistic concept of the state is also
possible without the concept of blood; in this connection I recall the concept
of the state of the Soviets, which is hostile to the peasantry and negates race,
but is by all means nationalistic, and the fascist concept of the state, which
affirms the rural population but negates the question of blood. It would be
wrong to extract individual elements from the uniform and unique whole of the
agrarian constitution and to transfer them to completely different subject areas
without the same natural and moral conditions being present there. It must
therefore be rejected when, in the controversy of opinions about the structure
of the industrial economy, the catchword „hereditary courts of the economy“ is
coined. For the peasant hereditary farm was not created in order to stabilize,
in the liberal-economic sense, an economic form which, for nationalistic
reasons, was somehow in need of protection, but which was worthy of
preservation, namely the peasant. Rather, the Erbhof was created solely to
preserve our blood for centuries to come.
It is the
preservation of the blood, of the race, that is important, not the economic
form. And this blood, according to all the experiences of our history, can be
preserved through generations only on peasant soil, not on urban soil. In
addition, however, the farmer must also enjoy economic protection because he
must always reckon with the uncertainties of weather and weather conditions,
which can be reduced to almost nothing in the city, because there one can make
oneself independent of them in the buildings. It is therefore, in my view, a
distortion of the National Socialist idea of peasants and hereditary farms to
speak of „hereditary farms of the economy“ in the commercial sector of the
economy. If there are enterprises in the commercial sector of the economy which
are to be preserved from being broken up by inheritance, or if, for reasons of a
healthy middle-class policy, it is desired that they be preserved in a family,
then a right of inheritance would suffice for this purpose, which would ensure
the transfer of the enterprise to a child. For this purpose, however, it is not
necessary to water down, so to speak, the peasant concept of the hereditary farm
of National Socialism and to turn it into the opposite, so that one no longer
mentions or foregrounds its actual task, the preservation of the blood for
generations to come, but does foreground the preservation of the economic form
of the farm, and in this way achieves a quite skewed representation of things.
The situation is similar with the concept of the entail, which is discussed
again and again in certain circles in public. In itself, from a purely
legislative point of view, there is no fundamental difference between the old
entail and the present National Socialist Erbhofgesetz, not even a difference in
degree: only the preconditions from which they were created and the objectives
they serve are different in the two institutions. In the Reichserbhof Law the
German people want to secure their existence for centuries to come, after
experience has taught them that they must look to the peasantry as the source of
their blood. The German peasantry has secured the existence of the people
through the centuries up to the present day, and from this realization the
legislator has drawn the logical conclusion. In the Fideikommifl, on the other
hand, a territorial principality wanted to stabilize a family that was valuable
to it and supported its rule, and it did so by protecting this family from the
increasingly noticeable mobilization of land as a result of the spread of
capitalism. Thus both institutions have in this a common fundamental idea, that
they preserve a race, that is, the blood, from economic accidents, and thus
protect it want to stabilize. While the Reichserbhof Law, however, was created
out of a national spirit and refers to the preservation of the German people as
a whole, and is therefore socialist, the idea of the entail presupposes a
territorial principality, for the stabilization of which the families devoted to
it are privileged. The Reichserbhofgesetz thus has a socialist portent, the
Fideikommiflrecht presupposes the return of territorial princely feudality.
Today, the
Reichserbh of Law is sufficient to link a family of great value to the German
people to the Scholle, even in the case of large landholdings, just as the
Fideikommifl did in the past. If, in spite of this, the question arises again
and again whether it would not be possible to create a right of entail in
addition to the Reichserbhof Law, this can only be explained by the fact that
certain circles still hope to be able to occupy a special position in National
Socialist Germany in the future because they once did so under other conditions
of constitutional law. Such circles completely forget that this question can be
answered in the affirmative for them only if their services to the National
Socialist State are as extraordinary as those to their former territorial rule,
so that they could also be extraordinarily rewarded.
That the National
Socialist State is prepared to take such an attitude it has proved in the case
of the family estate of the von Hindenburgs. It is also no secret when I declare
that the National Socialist Government is quite prepared to proceed along this
path and to reward extraordinary services to the State and the people in an
extraordinary way. This is quite in accordance with the National Socialist
principle that whoever assumes increased obligations in the service of the
German people may also enjoy corresponding privileges, but it is senseless to
demand from the present State privileges of past times without at least
presenting present services to this State as compensation. This is especially
true when one takes into account that the memory of the German people is not so
bad as to forget that the catastrophe of 1918 was due to a failure of its then
ruling class and that - what is perhaps even more significant here - the names
of this responsible and privileged ruling class, especially of the former owners
of the entailed estates, do not appear among the dead of Adolf Hitler’s freedom
movement, those dead who washed away with their blood a disgrace which the
political failure of those responsible at that time, after all, helped to bring
about. It should also be borne in mind that it was only through the sacrifice of
hundreds of dead under Adolf Hitler’s banner that it was possible to
re-establish legal conditions which today make it possible for us to have an
orderly constitutional state and protect us from Bolshevism. I therefore have no
understanding for today’s discussions on entailment, which lack any prerequisite
in terms of merit or blood in the National Socialist sense. The
Reichserbhofgesetz certainly gives the possibility of binding even large
estates, so to speak, in a fideicommiss like manner, if they meet the
requirements of § 5. However, this presupposes proof of the value of the lineage
in hereditary value or in its performance for the present State of Adolf Hitler,
for it is on the quality of the blood and its preservation that we are
concerned. In this sense we have also already made a number of larger estates,
which met the requirements of the Reichserbhof Law, into hereditary estates.
However, the Erbhof Law has no room for persons with a Jewish weaving defect in
their genealogical table, no matter how nice-sounding their names may be and how
well-sounding they may be in history. For this would be a contradiction in
terms, since the Erbhof Law, with a view to the German future, seeks to preserve
the blood source of the people, and that also means to keep it pure.
Unfortunately, practice proves that the resistance to the Reich Hereditary Court
Law on the part of individual large landowners must often be attributed to the
fact that the families concerned are afraid to correct a hitherto carefully
concealed defect in their genealogical table due to Jewish blood by applying for
recognition of their hereditary court. The only thing I can recommend today,
based on rich experience, is to always obtain a picture of the pedigree of such
opponents of the Reichserbhofgesetz, if possible, back to all
great-grandparents.
Today, on the basis of rich experience, I can only recommend that in the case of
such opponents of the Reichserbhof Law, one should always first obtain a picture
of their genealogical table, if possible back to all great-grandparents, before
one takes their opposition seriously from a factual point of view. With this I
may come to the conclusion: When the Deputy of the Fuehrer, Party Comrade Rudolf
Hess, said at the Reich Party Congress of the NSDAP. in Nuremberg in 1933 that
National Socialism meant nothing other than applied race science, he was saying
at the same time that for National Socialism the race question is not only the
key to understanding world history, as a witty Jew who knew something about
politics expressed it in one of his novels, but also that the race question
represents the axis of all political considerations of National Socialism. But
since no statesmanship in the world can disregard the earthly conditions of the
territory in which the people live, it is evident from this that the concepts of
„blood“ and „soil“ become the decisive fundamental idea of National Socialism.